There
is growing recognition that the problems with the federal government
will never be solved by the politicians in Washington, who created
them. They will never vote to reduce their power to spend, regulate
the rest of us, and perpetuate themselves in office. The national
debt is now $19 trillion—and growing—and 80,000 pages of new
federal regulations per year destroy our liberty and make our economy
less efficient, rendering us poorer than we otherwise would be. The
politicians use public spending for “good” purposes to “buy”
voter support that perpetuates themselves in office. As a result,
people are showing increasing interest in amending the Constitution
through its Article V procedure by the states, which leaves the
federal government out of the loop.
A
convention of states to consider amendments to the Constitution will
be called if two-thirds of the states so request. Any amendments
passed by the convention must then be approved by three-fourths of
the state legislatures. The most popular subjects for proposed
amendments are a balanced budget and term limits for elected
officials.
If
an amendments convention is called, it is unlikely that amending the
electoral college will be proposed, so why am I bringing this up
here? Because change will come, one way or other, due to
long-standing dissatisfaction with the electoral process. Over the
last two centuries there have been over 700 Constitutional amendments
proposed for the electoral college, far more than for any other
subject. None has met the criteria for adoption, but more will
undoubtedly be proposed. So it
is likely that sooner or later an amendment on this subject will be
passed.
In
addition to the possibility of changing the electoral process by
constitutional amendment, there is the possibility of simply
circumventing it by a compact of the states under the Constitution's
Compact Clause. There
is a National Popular Vote Interstate Compact movement attempting
this. Its scheme is to bypass the electoral college by states
agreeing in advance to cast all their electoral votes for the most
popular national candidate even if he doesn't win in their state.
This
agreement would go into effect only after enough states with the
electoral votes needed to win an election (270) join the purported
compact.
Under
this arrangement, the presidency could be determined by votes in as
few as eleven states. As frightening as that sounds, it is even more
frightening that 10 states and the District of Columbia with 165
electoral votes (61% of the necessary 270) have already signed up for
this.
There
are significant constitutional difficulties for the movement even if
it gets to 270
since the Compact Clause states: “No State shall, without the
Consent of Congress…enter into any Agreement or Compact with
another State.” But exceptions have been made. Moreover, one
should not place too much confidence in the Supreme Court's faithful
adherence to the Constitution when the Court has decided Obamacare is
constitutional and that the law authorizing Obamacare subsidies to
“exchanges established by the states” also applies to federal
exchanges contrary to the specific language and intent of Congress
performing its constitutional role.
So
we must be on our guard. Public opinion polls show that 70% of the
public believes the electoral college should be eliminated and
replaced by a national popular vote. No change should be made without
first understanding why the electoral college
was created, why the 12th Amendment, which destroyed it,
has precipitated 2 centuries of dissatisfaction and 700 efforts to
get rid of it, and why replacing it with a national popular vote
would be foolish.
Here
I must relate a little story. John Hospers was head of the
philosophy department at the University of Southern California for
twenty years. He was the author of nine books, the statement of
principles of the Libertarian Party, and was that party's first
nominee for president of the United States. He was the first person
ever to teach Ayn Rand's philosophy of Objectivism as part of a
university philosophy course. John was a big fan of my book Makers
and Takers
and even offered an endorsement for the back cover and quotes for
advertising that book. After that, we corresponded occasionally for
many years until his death. At one point he wrote me that a student
in one of his classes had asked, “Why don't we just abolish the
electoral college and elect a president by national popular vote?”
John told him, “Just you wait. I'm going to bring something
tomorrow that will answer your question.”
The
next day John brought his copy of my book Makers
and Takers and
stood up in front of the class and read aloud the entire
six-and-a-half pages I had written on the electoral college. He
delighted in telling me that the students were awestruck, simply
amazed at the subtleties embodied in this exquisitely designed
political instrument, some of which I
don't think even the Founders were aware of.
Everyone
knows that the Founders established three branches of government, the
executive, legislative and judicial, and hoped that each would
restrain the other two from exceeding their authority. But that is
only part of the system of checks and balances they established.
In
classical theory there were three types of government: monarchy,
oligarchy (or aristocracy), and democracy. These were, respectively,
rule by one, rule by a few, and rule by the many. The founders
considered which of these types would be best suited to each of the
three branches of government. There was, for example, some discussion
whether the presidency should be held by a single individual or a
committee. In the end the monarchical principle seemed best suited
to the executive branch. The Supreme Court and the Senate were
oligarchical in principle. Only one-half of one of the three
branches of government—the House of Representatives—would be
democratic.
That
is all the democracy the Founders intended. Supreme Court justices
were appointed—for life. The U.S. senators were chosen by the state
legislatures. And the president was chosen by the electoral college.
Albert Jay Nock once wrote, “One sometimes wonders how our
revolutionary forefathers would take it if they could hear some
flatulent political thimblerigger [i.e.swindler] charge them with
having founded 'the great and glorious democracy of the West.'”
What the Founders created was certainly not a democracy—which they
detested and feared. When at the Constitutional Convention delegate
James Wilson suggested choosing senators by popular vote, not a
single delegate supported him.
The
Founders created a mixed government drawn on the principles of
the three classical types. With the separation and balance of
the three branches of government, no one type
would predominate. The result is best described not as any one of
them but as a limited constitutional republic.
The
Founders wanted the people to have a voice in government. The
problem was how to give the individual a voice without
submitting government to the collective power of raw numbers.
It was highly desirable, as Madison expressed it, to structure
government so that it would have a tendency to “break and control”
the power of factions and guard against the “tyranny of the
majority,” which is based upon the rule of numbers, not upon
righteousness or excellence.
“A
mixed government was desirable,” wrote historian Clarence B.
Carson, “because there were differing functions of government which
could be best entrusted to one, to a few, or to many. But, if the
functions were best performed in this way, the division should not be
watered down by having all the branches chosen by the same
electorate.” The electorate for the House was the people. For the
Senate it was the states. But there was no convenient third
electorate for the presidency. One had to be created: the electoral
college.
The
states' power to chose their U.S. senators was an an important
check-and-balance feature of the Constitution. But that was
eliminated by the 17th Amendment, which made the Senate
democratic by requiring U.S. senators to be chosen by popular
election in the states.
The
17th
Amendment was a double tragedy for our Constitution. It not only
eliminated the only link between the states and the federal
government but destroyed the most important structural feature for
protecting individual rights. Safeguarding individual rights was not
one of the functions best performed by the many, the majority. It
was best left to a few. The Senate was the logical few. Madison saw
the Senate as a “necessary fence” against a majority “tempted
to commit injustice on the minority.” Edmund Randolph, governor
of Virginia and one of the more prominent men at the Constitutional
convention, said, “The object of this second branch [the Senate] is
to control the democratic branch of the National Legislature.” But
after the 17th
Amendment, the Senate became democratic too, unable to resist
democratic pressures within itself, much less restrain those in the
House.
Before,
when senators were elected by the states rather than the people
directly, senators could not be voted out by the majority if they
upheld the rights of the individual. Nor could they perpetuate
themselves in office by signing away some people's property or other
rights in exchange for votes of the majority. Senators could be more
concerned with doing what was right rather than what was popular.
Political decisions would tend to be made by superior thought rather
than superior numbers. “There is no maxim, in my opinion,” wrote
Madison, “which is more liable to be misapplied, and which,
therefore, more needs elucidation, than the current one, that the
interest of the majority is the political standard of right and
wrong.” After the 17th
amendment, senators--just like members of the House—found it
necessary to vote for more benefits to “buy” votes, or the public
would vote for others who would. Thus began a spending trend which
accelerated over the decades to where we now have a $19 trillion
dollar debt.
If
representation in the legislature were made proportional to
population, the large states would obviously be dominant and might
pass laws to their advantage at the expense of people in the smaller
states. Of course, the larger states objected to equal
representation, where all states would have the same number of
representatives irrespective of population. The solution was to have
two legislative bodies, one of each type, a House and a Senate. Each
state would have two senators, but its number of representatives in
the House would depend on its population. Any bills had to be passed
by both legislative bodies in order to become law. So neither the
large nor the small states could enact laws at the others' expense.
Laws could be passed only if they were generally considered
beneficial to both groups.
Members
of the House were to be elected directly by the people. But this
democratic feature was immediately balanced by the principle of
indirect election in the Senate. Gouverneur Morris said, “The
propensity of the first branch of the legislature to legislate too
much [and] to run into projects of paper money and similar
expedients” needed to be countered by the Senate. The popular was
to be balanced by the wise; the voice of the masses was to be
balanced by the wisdom of the few who were more knowledgeable than
the general public and selected from them by the filtering process of
indirect election.
The
Founders were well aware that not everyone had the same knowledge or
ability to make political decisions. If people elected from among
themselves those who were ablest, they in turn would be more likely
to make a wise elective decision than the populace as a whole.
Indirect elections thus tended to upgrade political selection by what
Madison referred to as a series of filtrations. “The effect,” he
wrote, “is to refine and enlarge the public views by passing them
through the medium of a chosen body of citizens, whose wisdom may
best discern the true interest of their country.”
The
electoral college was one of the most original and ingenious features
of our Constitution. Today it is probably the least understood. The
electoral college had all the advantages of indirect election just as
the Senate did. Indeed, some of these seemed more pronounced by the
fact the electors were selected for one task alone. They would have
nothing to gain politically because after casting their ballots they
would return to their private affairs. They
could not vote benefits from the public treasury to ingratiate
themselves with the voters and perpetuate themselves in office. It seemed, therefore, that
they would be even less susceptible to corruption or political
pressure and more likely than ever to exercise the wisdom and
independent judgment for which they were selected.
Each
state's representation in the electoral college was equal to its
representation in Congress, that is, to the total of its House
members plus its senators. In this way the exact numerical
composition of the legislative branch—which was acceptable to both
large and small states—was mirrored in the electoral college. But
that numerical composition was acceptable for the legislative branch
only because there were two legislative bodies, with power divided
and balanced between them. How was such a division and balance of
power to be achieved in the single body of the electoral collage?
While power in Congress was divided between two houses, in the
electoral college it was divided between two votes. The method of
voting was the electoral college's most ingenious and least
appreciated feature. Each elector was to vote for two men for
president. The candidate receiving the most votes would be the
president. The runner-up would be vice president.
An
obvious advantage of the method was that it provided that the vice
president would be the man regarded as the second most qualified to
be president, rather than just someone chosen to balance the ticket
geographically or for some other political reason. There were,
however, subtler but even more important advantages to the system.
The
requirement that each elector's votes be split between two candidates
tended to “break and control” the power of factions. It cut the
democratic power of numbers. It limited the political effects of the
larger states numerical strength and prevented them from dominating
presidential elections.
While
it might be expected that electors would show some partiality to
candidates from their own states, this factor would be offset by the
requirement that each elector cast at least one vote for someone
outside his state. At least half the votes were thus more likely to
reflect merit rather than state politics or factions. The voting was
deliberately structured to minimize the influence of local political
ties or indebtedness and maximize the independent reasoning of the
electors. Since electors could be expected to some extent to vote
for leading figures from their own states—not only for political
reasons but because they might know their qualifications better—such
votes would in large measure cancel each other. Important and often
decisive, then, would be those votes candidates would receive from
outside
their states, votes reflecting the impartial judgment of electors who
had no political obligations and nothing to gain. The dominant power
in electing the president would thus rest not with the states which
had most to gain, by electing one of their own men, but with the
votes from states which had the
least
to gain, just as with the electors themselves. (The exact opposite
would be true if the president were popularly elected.)
Consequently, with the original system there would be little tendency
to choose a president on the basis of gaining benefits for some at
others' expense.
In
the election in 1800 two men had the same number of electoral votes.
This happened because the electors did not vote for two men for the
presidency. They expected Jefferson would be president and cast their
second vote for their choice as vice president. In his book
on the electoral college, Roger Lea McBride writes, “It is probable
that few people outside his own circle wanted him [Aaron Burr] to be
president—and if the electors had voted according to their own
convictions, he would never have been a real contender for the job.”
The electors didn't want him for president, but he was politically
powerful in New York, the nation's largest state, and would balance
the ticket by being from the North. (Jefferson was from Virginia.)
With
Burr and Jefferson having the same number of electoral votes, the
election was thrown into the House of Representatives, where the
scoundrel Burr made a bold attempt to gain the presidency. He
collaborated with opposition members in the House, persuading them to
vote for him for president. After thirty-five ballots, the contest
was still deadlocked. Finally Alexander Hamilton prevailed upon
several members of his party to cast blank votes allowing Jefferson
to be elected. And the 12th amendment to the
Constitution, which provided separate ballots for president and vice
president, ensued to prevent the situation from occurring again.
Hamilton's
solution was a quick fix for the immediate problem of electing a
president then, but the change required by the 12th
Amendment has been so unsatisfactory that more than 700 amendments
have been proposed for altering it.
The
original electoral system of voting for two candidates had
fascinating implications. It might well be that the elector would
feel obligated to vote for the most popular candidate among the
people he represented. He might even be pledged to do so. But he
would have a second vote to cast. Having cast one vote for the
popular choice, he might be more inclined to exercise his own
judgment on the second. Both would count the same. In this event
the electoral college would represent a balance between the numerical
power of the people and the independent judgment of the electors, and
the choice of the president would reflect some combination of the
two.
No
less intriguing would be the consequences if the elector reflected
popular sentiment in his second vote as well. Suppose instead of
exercising independent judgment he cast the second vote for the
second most popular candidate in his state. Both votes would be
equal. The majority would have no advantage—with obvious
implications for minority rights. There would be little political
incentive for making lavish campaign promises to gain votes of the
majority at the expense of the minority if the minority were equally
important politically.
With
such a system it would be possible for a man to be elected president
who did not carry a single state in popular vote. He could
accumulate a winning total of electoral votes by finishing second in
a great many states if several different candidates won in those
states, each winning only a few. In this situation the man with all
the second places finishes would indeed have the broadest political
support across the country. Under today's system he wouldn't get a
single electoral vote.
If
a candidate could receive electoral votes for finishing second, the
whole power structure of the two-party system wouldn't have developed
in the way that it has. Where the winner takes all the votes under
the present system, there can be only two significant parties, both
contesting for the majority position. Only the majority on a
state-wide basis has any representation in the electoral college.
One party is the majority; the other hopes to become the majority and
has the best chance of doing so. All its hopes and its influence
rest on becoming the majority, because it has no representation as a
minority. If, however, each elector cast two votes for the
presidency, one representing whoever came in second, both the
majority and the principal minority would be represented. There
would be political value to being that minority, not just to being
the majority. Second place would be worth fighting for, whereas only
first place is today. As a result, third parties could effectively
contest the second position for the same reason that only two can do
so for the top spot in the present winner-take-all system.
Under
the present two-party system the greater the dominance of one party
in a state, the less important the other becomes, because the more
remote is its chance of becoming the majority, which is the only way
of winning electoral votes. Under a two-vote electoral system, where
the runner-up would receive the second vote, the greater dominance of
one party would make it more attractive for third parities to
compete. In a state where, let's say, eighty percent of the people
vote for one party, a third party would need to gain only little more
than half of the remaining twenty percent to obtain electoral
representation.
Under
the present two-party system, the greater the dominance of one party,
the less sensitive it is to the rights of individuals in the
minority, because it becomes more difficult for the minority to
protect themselves. Under a two-vote electoral system, with the
second vote representing the runner-up, the minority represented by
that vote would have the electoral power to balance the majority
regardless of the size of the majority. For example, if the
runner-up had only twenty percent of the popular vote in a state or
district, compared to 80 percent for the majority candidate, the
former would have the same power to balance the latter as if the vote
totals were 49 to 51 percent or even 50-50. Thus the two-vote
electoral system was another clever way of protecting the rights of
individuals in the minority from the power and desires of the
majority.
We
shall never know whether or how the electoral college would have
utilized these possibilities had the two-vote system been retained,
but the potential was there. It was intrinsic to the mechanism.
The
12th Amendment altered the electoral college to provide
for separate ballots for the president and vice president, with each
elector casting one vote for each. Gone were all the advantages of
the two-vote system. Overnight the large states doubled their power
to advance their own candidates and amplified the power of the
majority. Minorities which might have been represented by the second
vote under the original system, no longer had any representation.
Without
the requirement of splitting votes between two presidential
candidates, block voting for a single candidate became the practice.
By casting its votes as a block, a state could increase its electoral
power relative to those states that still divided their votes among
two or more candidates. To maintain its share of influence, every
state soon found it necessary to cast all its votes as a block. The
system which originally mitigated the power of superior numbers was
turned into one which exemplified them.
While
the new system limited electors to a single choice on their ballots,
the block-voting practice dictated that it would be the popular
choice. Although the electors might have voted individually on the
basis of their own minds, there was no way they could do so
collectively. Voting collectively, as a block, inevitably meant
voting on a physical rather than an intellectual basis, voting on the
basis of herd power rather than reasoning. The electoral system,
which was originally designed to reflect superior judgment, became a
mechanical system where that judgment could not be exercised.
After
the Jefferson-Burr crisis, a change was clearly needed, but it did
not have be one that amplified the power of the majority and
destroyed the advantages of the original system. All that was
necessary was to have separate ballots for president and vice
president but to allow each elector two votes for each, one of each
being for someone outside his state. Now, however, we need more than
that because of the 17th Amendment (popular election of
senators) and the emergence of block voting.
The
Senate is no longer a bulwark for the protection of individual
rights, as the Founders intended. Ideally, we should repeal the 17th
Amendment, but there is no chance of that happening. The best we can
hope for is to change the 12th Amendment to reflect the
Founders' intent to elect a president through the filtering effect of
indirect election and incorporating reasoned judgment—not merely
numerical superiority—which would help to protect individual rights
from the “tyranny of the majority.”
We
need to return to the idea of the electors exercising their
independent judgment, as the Founders intended. To the Founders, the
word “ballot” meant secret ballot. That would allow the
electors to exercise their discretion, free from any attempt to
control their vote. Twenty-nine states and the District of Columbia
have laws purporting to bind electors to the state's popular vote.
Some even prescribe fines or criminal penalties for violation. Others
demand resignation of the elector and cancellation of the ballot.
Appellate and constitutional lawyers Rivkin and Grossman write
that though these laws have never been enforced, “nonetheless,
their very existence misleads the public and, even worse, chills
electors from discharging their duty to exercise judgment. The time
is ripe to put an end to this legal charade and establish, as
federal-court precedent, that the Constitution forbids enforcement of
elector-binding mandates.”
State
courts have held that elector pledges cannot impose a legal
obligation. For example, the Supreme Court of Ohio in 1948 concluded
that when a state attempts to “dictate to the electors the choice
which they must make for president and vice president, it has invaded
the field set apart to the electors by the Constitution of the United
States, and such action cannot stand.”
What
we need, therefore, is a constitutional amendment providing each
elector cast two secret
ballots: one ballot with two names for president, and one ballot with
two names for vice president. Each of these ballots shall have at
least one name from outside the elector's home state. No
state shall mandate for whom an elector's votes shall be cast.
Restoring
the independent judgment of electors could be important in another
respect. What if the winner of the popular vote dies or is
incapacitated during the weeks between his election and the voting of
the Electoral college? Or what about corruption, delays or trouble
with state ballots? What if a candidate is revealed to have, say,
Parkinson's disease or other progressive disease that has been kept
from the public but make it unlikely that person would have full
capabilities—or even survive—for a full term as president? Should
electors still be pledged to vote for that person? Federal law
provides no guidance on how to respond, but the Founders intended
that electors would exercise appropriate judgment if such
contingencies should arise.
election
of our third president.
the
great danger for democracy, according to Tocqueville, is the rise of
“democratic despotism,” e great danger for democracy, according
to Tocqueville, is the rise of “democratic despotism,” he great
danger for democracy, according to Tocqueville, is the rise of
“democratic despotism,” There is no maxim, in my opinion, which
is more liable to be misapplied, and which, t
ore
needs elucidation, than the current one, that the interest of the
majority is the political standard of right and wrong.”--James
Madison “There
is no maxim, in my opinion, which is more liable to be misapplied,
and which, therefore, more needs elucidation, than the current one,
that the interest of the majority is the political standard of right
and wrong.”--James Madison